Intertemporal Social Welfare

a dark satanic mill

________________________________________________________

"[Harrod] declared himself a "cardinalist" and pointed in particular to the fact that cardinal utility is necessary in dynamic analysis. With this I am in complete agreement. It is indeed the gospel I have tried to preach for nearly a generation. To me, the idea that cardinal utility should be avoided in economic theory is completely sterile. It is derived from a very special and indeed narrow part of the theory, viz., that of static equilibrium."

(Ragnar Frisch, 1964, "Dynamic Utility", Econometrica)

"In the case of the individual, pure time preference is irrational, it means that he is not viewing all moments as equally parts of one life. In the case of society, pure time preference is unjust: it means...that the living take advantage of their position in time to favor their own interests."

(John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971: p.295)

________________________________________________________

Back

Contents

    (1) Intertemporal Social Welfare Functions
    (2) The Defense of Discounting
            (A) The Tastes Defense
            (B) The Dynastic Defense
            (C) The Decentralization Defense
    (3) The Koopmans Axiomatization
    (4) Population Growth
    (5) Overlapping Generations
    (6) Varying Time Preference
    (7) Intertemporal Justice
            (A) Rawlsian Social Welfare
            (B) Rawlsian Altruism


Optimal growth theory was initiated by Frank Ramsey (1928) as an exercise in normative economics. As outlined in our introduction, the Ramsey exercise was geared to address Arthur Pigou's (1920: Part I, Ch. 2) concerns about the implications for society's savings of the personal "irrationality" of discounting future utility. Effectively, Ramsey demonstrated that an economy in which people have positive time preference will save far below what is optimal -- exactly as Pigou predicted.

The practical implications are self-evident: if time preference does lead people to "save too little", perhaps the government should step in and "force" them to save. As Pigou concluded, "there is wide agreement that the State should protect the interests of the future in some degree against the effects of our irrational discounting and of our preferences for ourselves over our descendants." (Pigou, 1920: p.29). Public pension systems such as the American "Social Security" program were designed precisely with this goal in mind.

But Ramsey's (1928) "proof" that a society composed of people with positive time preference saved too little depended heavily on how he determined the "optimal" level of savings. Ramsey determined this with perfectly Benthamite instincts: he looked for the optimal allocation of consumption across generations which maximized intertemporal "social welfare", defined as the sum of individual utilities across generations. This has led to much debate and what follows is a rather lengthy, but by no means deep, digression on "intertemporal" social welfare functions, with particular attention paid to the concept of "time preference".

 

backBack topTop Selected References

nextNext

 

top1.gif (924 bytes)Top
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

All rights reserved, Gonçalo L. Fonseca