Profile Major Works Resources

William Whewell, 1794-1866.

Portrait of W. Whewell

Cambridge polymath - mathematician, scientist, moral philosopher, theologian, educator and economist.  As one contemporary put it, "science is his forte, omniscience is his foible".

William Whewell was born in Lancaster, the son of a carpenter. Young William's outstanding performance in his early schooling caught the attention of schoolmasters, and led his father to reluctantly consent to his further education, rather than apprenticing him off. After a period at grammar schools in Lancaster, topped off at Haversham school, William Whewell entered Trinity College, Cambridge in 1812, where he would end up spending the rest of his life. Whewell made second wrangler and obtained his B.A. in 1816. After a period as a private tutor,. Whewell was elected fellow of Trinity College in 1817 and assistant tutor in mathematics.

In his youth, Whewell drank deeply from continental sources - particularly the German philosophy of Immanuel Kant and the French mathematical science of Lagrange and Laplace. Cambridge, then still lumbering on with its Scholastic curriculum and bizarre Tripos, had fallen well behind. Early in his time at Cambridge, Whewell had met and befriended the astronomer John F.W. Herschel, Charles Babbage, George Peacock and the economist Richard Jones and several other bright lights. Whewell & Co. founded the Cambridge Philosophical Society in 1819, with the goal of bringing modern continental science to Britain   Whewell's first textbook, Elementary Treatise on Mechanics (1819) imported the French analytical tradition, applying the new mathematics to other sciences.   Whewell was elected to the Royal Society in 1820, and became a lecturer in mathematics at Trinity.

In 1825, William Whewell was ordained an Anglican priest.  That same year, the Cambridge chair in mineralogy fell vacant, and Whewell made his mind to compete for it.  He spent the next few years on long vacations in Germany studying the subject (as well as Gothic churches and Romantic literature, for which he maintained a lifelong devotion), and finally secured the position of professor of mineralogy at Cambridge in 1828.  Whewell promptly put out a small tract on mineralogy, but his next few years would be marked by an veritable explosion in productivity in other topics. 

For economists, the most memorable was undoubtedly Whewell's "Mathematical Exposition", a series of essays read before the Cambridge Philosophical Society (1829, 1830) translating most of the extant Ricardian economic theory into mathematics. The endeavor was not warmly welcomed by many contemporaries, and Whewell exercise was partly polemical - to prove that Ricardo's theory was mistaken, that even accepting his premises, one reached the opposite conclusions.  Whewell showed the usefulness of mathematical methods, and expressed his confidence that mathematics could be applied as successfully to economics as to the physical mechanics.  But he also wanted to emphasize the problem of the premises. Mechanics was successful because it was careful with its premises, which it only established after much careful observation and experimentation.  Economists, by contrast, seem happy to pluck their assumptions from a priori reflection, speculation and slapdash simplification.  As a result, their premises were incomplete and inadequate, and so long as economists approached them that way, economics would remain far behind mechanics, no matter how much mathematics was thrown at it.  This latter observation had been impressed upon Whewell by Richard Jones.  Friends from their Cambridge days, Whewell and Jones had maintained a close intellectual relationship through the 1820s.  Jones, a thorough British empiricist to the bone, was always a little suspicious and occasionally impatient with Whewell's analytical proclivities.  Jones had always tried to curb Whewell's wide-eyed belief that the moral sciences, law even theology, could be reduced to a grand over-arching natural philosophy with the precision of mechanics. Jones impressed upon Whewell the importance of empirical facts in the construction of theory, and nudged Whewell in that direction.  In 1831, Jones wrote a blistering critique of the Ricardians, and added an barely-concealed condemnation of the logical-deductivist methodology espoused by the Catallacticists of Oxford.  In his (anonymous) review of Jones for the British Critic, Whewell joined in the fray.

The collaboration with Jones on economics was vital in transitioning Whewell's perspective from analytical youth to mature empiricist  Whewell and Jones formed the kernel of what can be called the "English Historical School".  The Cambridge empiricist crew (Whewell, Jones, Babbage and, one might add the elderly Malthus) positioned themselves against both the abstractness of the Ricardians of London and the logical-deductivist Catallacticists of Oxford.   The collection of facts must precede the construction of theory, and to that end promoted the advance of data-collection and statistics.    Nonetheless, Whewell's attempts to fit mathematical demand curves to data and his derivation of an equilibrium in trade in a 1850 article  have led some to consider him a  proto-Marginalist.  

Whewell was one of the founders of the British Association for the Advancement of Science (BAAS) in 1831  Whewell invited the pioneering Belgian statistician Adolphe Quetelet to the BAAS meetings in Cambridge in 1832.  The Cambridge empiricist crew, led by Whewell, promptly persuaded the BAAS to add "Section F" ("Statistics", soon to include "Economic Science") in 1833, the first open professional organization of economists in Britain. The same crew led the effort the next year to found the Statistical Society of London in 1834. 

In 1833, Whewell contributed a notable essay on astronomy as part of the Bridgewater Treatises on natural theology.  Loosely, Whewell's basic argument was that knowledge of the world is acquired because there are "fundamental" and uniform laws of science which we are able to discover.   Whewell took this as evidence of the existence of a divinity to provide such uniformity.  These underlying scientific laws of the world are precisely the "Ideas" that God used in his creation of it.  Taking it a step further, Whewell went on to argue that science, by "discovering" these laws, was itself a providential task as it brought men closer to understanding the majesty of God's design.

Whewell articulated his empiricist view of science more generally in his two monumental treatises, History of the Inductive Sciences (1837) and  Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences (1840)   Whewell is often regarded as the father of modern philosophy of science. 

Whewell is best known for his theory of induction (which led up to a sharp debate with the more empirically-minded John Stuart Mill).  The "sharing" of human mind and physical phenomena was used by Whewell to argue that a priori ideas were necessarily "true" in an empirical sense.  Because mind and world are synchronized by the same principle, human intuition and empirical evidence tend to achieve the same results.  To use a famous example, Whewell did not accept that 2 + 1 = 3 on the grounds that it was a tautology (i.e. "2 + 1 is the definition of 3", as argued by Condillac and James Mill) nor because it was an empirical fact ("experience shows that a triple of things can be divided into a double and a single", as argued by John Stuart Mill).  Instead, Whewell argued that because it is inconceivable to think that 2 + 1 is not equal to 3, therefore 2 + 1 = 3.  Empirical evidence merely confirms this natural intuition, but it is not the cause of it.

Whewell was also an able pedagogue with an important role in reorganizing Trinity College, Cambridge. Whewell was critical in introducing the "moral sciences" and "natural sciences" examinations at Cambridge in 1848.  He was also notable wordsmith, e.g. the positive/negative charge language for electro-chemistry used since Faraday and even  the terms "scientist" and "physicist" in their modern meaning are originally due to Whewell.

 

  


top1.gif (924 bytes)Top

Major works of William Whewell

  • An Elementary Treatise on Mechanics, 1819, [bk], [1824 2nd ed], [1833 4th ed; additions offp], [1836 5th ed], [1847 7th ed]
  • A Treatise on Dynamics, containing a considerable collection of mechanical problems, 1823 [bk]
  • An Essay on Mineralogical Classification and Nomenclature, 1828 [bk] [1842 3rd ed]
  • Architectural Notes on German Churches, with remarks on the origins of Gothic architecture, 1830. [bk]
  • "A Mathematical Exposition of Some Doctrines of Political Economy", (read March, 1829, pub. 1830), Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, p.191
  • [Anon] "Jones on the Distribution of Wealth and Source of Taxation", 1831, British Critic, (July) p.41
  • "Mathematical Exposition of Some Leading Doctrines in Mr. Ricardo's Principles of Political Economy and Taxation'" (read Apr-May 1831, pub. 1833), Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, p.155
  • The First Principles of Mechanics, with historical and practical illustrations, 1832 [bk]
  • An Introduction to Dynamics, containing the laws of motion and the first three sections of the Principia, 1832 [bk]
  • On the Free Motion of Points, and on Universal Gravitation, including the principal propositions of books I. and III. of the Principia; the first part of a new edition of the Treatise on Dynamics, 1832 [bk], [1836 ed]
  • Astronomy and General Physics considered with reference to Natural Theology - Bridgewater Treatise No. 3, 1833 [bk] [1834 repr]
  • "Essay Towards the First Approximation to a Map of Cotidal Lines", 1833, Philosophical Transactions of Royal Society, p.147 [1833 offp]
  • Analytical Statics, a supplement to the fourth edition of an Elementary Treatise on Mechanics, 1833 [bk]
  • On the Motion of Points constrained and resisted, and on the motion of a rigid body: the second part of a new edition of a Treatise on dynamics, 1834 [bk]
  • Remarks on some parts of Mr. Thirlwall's Letter on the admission of Dissenters to academical degrees, 1834 [bk]
  • Additional Remarks on some parts of Mr. Thirlwall's Two Letters on the admission of Dissenters to academical degrees, 1834 [bk]
  • Newton and Flamsteed, remarks on an article in number CIX of the Quarterly review, to which are added two letters occasioned by a note in number CX of the Review, 1836 [bk]
  • Thoughts on the Study of Mathematics as part of a Liberal Education, 1836 [1838 Principles, ed. p.135, with Additional Thoughts, p.177, with letter to the editor of the Edinburgh Review, p.186
  • History of the Inductive Sciences, from the earliest to the present times, 1837 v.1, v.2, v.3. [1847 2nd ed., v.1, v.2, v.3][1857 3rd ed, v.1, v.2, v.3], [1859 US repr, v.1, v.2], [1901 repr, v.1, v.2]
  • On the Principles of English University Education, 1837 [bk] [1838 2nd ed]
  • On the Foundations of Morals, four sermons preached before the University of Cambridge, November, 1837, 1837 [1839, 2nd ed. US ed]
  • The Mechanical Euclid, containing the elements of mechanics and hydrostatics demonstrated after the manner of the elements of geometry; and including the propositions fixed Upon by the University of Cambridge as requisite for the degree of B.A. to which are added Remarks on Mathematical Reasoning and on the Logic of Induction, 1837 [bk; remarks Pt.1 (p.143), Pt. 2 (p.172)] [1838 3rd ed]
  • The Doctrine of Limits, with its applications, namely, conic sections, the first three sections of Newton, the differential calculus, 1838 [bk]
  • Address delivered at the Anniversary Meeting of the Geological Society of London, on the 16th of February 1838, 1838 [bk]
  • The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, founded upon their history, 1840 v.1, v.2   [1847 2nd ed., v.1, v.2].
  • Aphorisms concerning Ideas, Science & the Language of Science, 1840 [bk]
  • Two Introductory Lectures to Two Courses of Lectures on Moral Philosophy, delivered in 1839 and 1841, 1841 [bk]
  • The Mechanics of Engineering, 1841 [bk]
  • The Elements of Morality, including Polity, 1845 v.1, v.2 [moa1, moa2] [1848 new ed, v.1, v.2]
  • Indications of the Creator: extracts, bearing upon theology, from the history and the philosophy of the inductive sciences, 1845 [bk] [1846 2nd ed]
  • Of a Liberal Education in General, and with particular reference to the leading studies of the University of Cambridge, 1845 [bk] [1850 2nd ed: v.1, v.2]
  • Lectures on Systematic Morality, delivered in Lent Term, 1846, 1846 [bk]
  • Conic sections, their principal properties proved geometrically, 1846 [bk] [1855 3rd ed]
  • "Strictures on Dr. Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences", 1847, Colburn's United Service Magazine, Pt.1 (p.161), Pt. 2 (p.367) [1847 offpr]
  • Sunday Thoughts and Other Verses, 1847
  • "Criticism of Aristotle's Account of Induction", (read 1850,  pub. 1856),Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, p.63
  • "Mathematical Exposition of Certain Doctrines of Political Economy", (read 1850, pub. 1856),Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, p.128
  • Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy in England, 1852 [bk]
  • Astronomy and General Physics: Considered with reference to natural theology, 1852-6. [moa]
  • "On the influence of the history of Science upon intellectual education", 1854, Lectures on Education, delivered at the Royal Institution of Great Britain, p.1.
  • The Plurality of Worlds,  [1854 US ed] [1858 2nd US edmoa]
  • History of Scientific Ideas, being the second part of the philosophy of inductive sciences, 1858 ["3rd ed", v.1, v.2]
  • Novum Organon Renovatum, being the second part of the philosophy of inductive sciences, 1858 ["3rd.ed" bk]]
  • "Prefactory Note" to Richard Jones (1859), Literary Remains, p.ix
  • On the Philosophy of Discovery, chapters historical and critical, including the completion of the third edition of the philosophy of inductive sciences, 1860 [bk]
  • Six Lectures Delivered on Political Economy, delivered at Cambridge in Michaelmas term 1861, 1862 [bk, av]. [McM: pdf; html]

 


HET

 

top1.gif (924 bytes)Top

Resources on William Whewell

  • "The Bridgewater Treatises - The Universe and its Author", 1833, Quarterly Review (no.99, Oct), p.1 (review of Whewell and Chalmers).
  • "The Bridgewater Bequest - Whewell's Astronomy and General Physics" by [David Brewster], 1834, Edinburgh Review (no.118, Jan ), p.422
  • "Report of the Proceedings of the Council of the Royal Society", 1838, Philosophical Magazine, p.341 (on Whewell's research on tides)
  • "Account of the Rev. John Flamsteed", 1835, Quarterly Review, (Dec. No. 109), p.96
  • "Note on Mr. Whewell's pamphlet, entitled 'Newton and Flamsteed'", 1836, Quarterly Review, (Feb, No. 110), p.568.
  • "Study of Mathematics - University of Cambridge" 1836, Edinburgh Review, (Jan, No. 126) p.409
  • "Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences" by [David Brewster],  1837 Edinburgh Review (No. 133, Oct), p.110
  • "Whewell's Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences", by [David Brewster],  1842, Edinburgh Review, (No.150, Jan), p.265
  • "University Education", by [Alexander Bain] 1848, Westminster Review, (Jul) p.441 (review of Whewell)
  • William Whewell, D. D., Master of Trinity College, Cambridge: An Account of His Writings with Selections from His Literary and Scientific Correspondence, by Isaac Todhunter, 1876, v.1, v.2
  • The Life and Selections from the Correspondence of William Whewell, D.D., late master of Trinity College Cambridge, by Janet Stair Douglas, 1881 [bk] [1882 2nd ed]
  • "William Whewell", by Harvey Carlisle, 1882, Macmillan's Magazine, p.138
  • "Whewell, William" in R.H. Inglis Palgrave, editor, 1894-1899, Dictionary of Political Economy [1918 ed.]
  • "Whewell, William" in Leslie Stephen & Stephen Lee, editor, 1885-1901 Dictionary of National Biography [1908-09 ed]
  • "Whewell, William" in 1911 Encyclopaedia Britannica.
  • Whewell page at McMaster
  • Whewell page at MacTutor
  • "The Whewell-Mill Debate in a Nutshell" by Malcolm R. Forster and Ann Wolfe [online]
  • "The Debate between Whewell and Mill on the Nature of Scientific Induction" by Malcom Forster, 2009, History of Logic [pdf]
  • "Natural Theology, Victorian Periodicals and the Fragmentation of a Common Context", by Robert M. Young, Darwin's Metaphor [online]
  • William Whewell Archives at Trinity College, Cambridge
  • Whewell Page at Lancaster
  • "Architecture and Induction: Whewell and Ruskin on Gothic" by Jonathan Smith
  • Reviews of Edward O. Wilson's Consilience in the National Review and the American Scholar
  • See also "Consilience Revisited" by Laura Walls and "Consilience" by Richard Rorty.
  • "The Fall and Rise of Catastrophism" by Trevor Palmer 
  • Whewell page at Victorian Web
  • Whewell entry at Stanford Encycl of Philosophy
  • Whewell entry at 1968 IESS (Encyclopedia.com)
  • Whewell entry at Biog Dictionary of Astronomers
  • Whewell entry at Britannica
  • Whewell online books page at U Penn.
  • Wikipedia

 

 
top1.gif (924 bytes)Top
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

All rights reserved, Gonçalo L. Fonseca